in the Stoic philosophy, who was constantly in his
train and usually attended him even on journeys, knew
how to adapt the system to clever men of the world,
to keep its speculative side in the background, and
to modify in some measure the dryness of the terminology
and the insipidity of its moral catechism, more particularly
by calling in the aid of the earlier philosophers,
among whom Scipio himself had an especial predilection
for the Socrates of Xenophon. Thenceforth the
most noted statesmen and scholars professed the Stoic
philosophy—among others Stilo and Quintus
Scaevola, the founders of scientific philology and
of scientific jurisprudence. The scholastic
formality of system, which thenceforth prevails at
least externally in these professional sciences and
is especially associated with a fanciful, charade-like,
insipid method of etymologizing, descends from the
Stoa. But infinitely more important was the new
state-philosophy and state-religion, which emanated
from the blending of the Stoic philosophy and the
Roman religion. The speculative element, from
the first impressed with but little energy on the system
of Zeno, and still further weakened when that system
found admission to Rome—after the Greek
schoolmasters had already for a century been busied
in driving this philosophy into boys’ heads and
thereby driving the spirit out of it—fell
completely into the shade in Rome, where nobody speculated
but the money-changers; little more was said as to
the ideal development of the God ruling in the soul
of man, or of the divine world-law. The Stoic
philosophers showed themselves not insensible to the
very lucrative distinction of seeing their system
raised into the semi-official Roman state-philosophy,
and proved altogether more pliant than from their
rigorous principles we should have expected.
Their doctrine as to the gods and the state soon exhibited
a singular family resemblance to the actual institutions
of those who gave them bread; instead of illustrating
the cosmopolitan state of the philosopher, they made
their meditations turn on the wise arrangement of the
Roman magistracies; and while the more refined Stoics
such as Panaetius had left the question of divine
revelation by wonders and signs open as a thing conceivable
but uncertain, and had decidedly rejected astrology,
his immediate successors contended for that doctrine
of revelation or, in other words, for the Roman augural
discipline as rigidly and firmly as for any other maxim
of the school, and made extremely unphilosophical
concessions even to astrology. The leading feature
of the system came more and more to be its casuistic
doctrine of duties. It suited itself to the
hollow pride of virtue, in which the Romans of this
period sought their compensation amidst the various
humbling circumstances of their contact with the Greeks;
and it put into formal shape a befitting dogmatism
of morality, which, like every well-bred system of
morals, combined with the most rigid precision as a
whole the most complaisant indulgence in the details.(9)
Its practical results can hardly be estimated as
much more than that, as we have said, two or three
families of rank ate poor fare to please the Stoa.