all tragic art—that action is passion—holds
true no doubt also of ancient tragedy; it exhibits
man in action, but it makes no real attempt to individualize
him. The unsurpassed grandeur with which the
struggle between man and destiny fulfils its course
in Aeschylus depends substantially on the circumstance,
that each of the contending powers is only conceived
broadly and generally; the essential humanity in Prometheus
and Agamemnon is but slightly tinged by poetic individualizing.
Sophocles seizes human nature under its general conditions,
the king, the old man, the sister; but not one of
his figures displays the microcosm of man in all his
aspects—the features of individual character.
A high stage was here reached, but not the highest;
the delineation of man in his entireness and the entwining
of these individual—in themselves finished—figures
into a higher poetical whole form a greater achievement,
and therefore, as compared with Shakespeare, Aeschylus
and Sophocles represent imperfect stages of development.
But, when Euripides undertook to present man as he
is, the advance was logical and in a certain sense
historical rather than poetical. He was able
to destroy the ancient tragedy, but not to create the
modern. Everywhere he halted half-way.
Masks, through which the expression of the life of
the soul is, as it were, translated from the particular
into the general, were as necessary for the typical
tragedy of antiquity as they are incompatible with
the tragedy of character; but Euripides retained them.
With remarkably delicate tact the older tragedy had
never presented the dramatic element, to which it was
unable to allow free scope, unmixed, but had constantly
fettered it in some measure by epic subjects from
the superhuman world of gods and heroes and by the
lyrical choruses. One feels that Euripides was
impatient under these fetters: with his subjects
he came down at least to semi-historic times, and
his choral chants were of so subordinate importance,
that they were frequently omitted in subsequent performance
and hardly to the injury of the pieces; but yet he
has neither placed his figures wholly on the ground
of reality, nor entirely thrown aside the chorus.
Throughout and on all sides he is the full exponent
of an age in which, on the one hand, the grandest
historical and philosophical movement was going forward,
but in which, on the other hand, the primitive fountain
of all poetry—a pure and homely national
life—had become turbid. While the
reverential piety of the older tragedians sheds over
their pieces as it were a reflected radiance of heaven;
while the limitation of the narrow horizon of the
older Hellenes exercises its satisfying power even
over the hearer; the world of Euripides appears in
the pale glimmer of speculation as much denuded of
gods as it is spiritualised, and gloomy passions shoot
like lightnings athwart the gray clouds. The
old deeply-rooted faith in destiny has disappeared;
fate governs as an outwardly despotic power, and the