This was asserted as a matter of fact, observed from
and confirmed by experience. But what does it
signify? To what causes is this familiar fact
to be attributed? The first stage of the answer
is very ample. The many individuals, whose purchases
make up the demand for the commodity, will buy smaller
quantities now that the price is higher. Possibly
some of them may cease to buy it altogether; but as
a rule it would be reasonable to suppose that most
people continue to buy a certain amount though a smaller
amount than hitherto. Let us turn our attention,
then, to the individual purchaser, and ask ourselves
why he (or let us say she) acts in the manner indicated.
The obvious answer is that the more she already has
of anything, the less urgently does she require a
little more of it. If she buys 6 pounds of sugar
every week when the price is 7 cents a pound, but
only 5 pounds when the price is 8 cents, she shows
by her action that she does not consider that the
additional utility she will derive from buying 6 pounds
a week rather then 5 pounds is worth as much as 8
cents. But she shows at the same time that she
thinks it worth 7 cents. For, when the price
is 7 cents, no one compels her to buy that sixth pound.
She could stop, if she chose, at five; and it may
serve to make the point quite plain if we suppose
her actually to hesitate before she buys the sixth.
She has hitherto, let us say, been buying 5 pounds
a week at 8 cents. To-day she enters the shop
and finds the price is down to 7 cents. She asks
for her customary 5 pounds; then she pauses, and a
minute later turns her order into six. What are
the alternatives which she has been weighing one against
the other in that momentary pause? Not the utility
of the whole 6 pounds of sugar against the total price
of 42 cents. For she has already ordered the first
5 pounds; and the decision to buy the sixth is taken
independently and subsequently. She has been
sizing up the
increment of utility which a sixth
pound would yield, and she decides that this is worth
the expenditure of a further 7 cents. Again,
when the price was 8 cents she need not have bought
as many as 5 pounds. She could have stopped at
4 had she chosen, and the fact that she did buy 5
pounds shows that the increment of utility derived
from buying a fifth pound, when she might be said
already to have 4, was worth at least 8 cents in her
judgment.
This trite illustration enables us to lay down two
important laws relating to utility. To state
them shortly, it is convenient to employ one or two
technical terms, which, unlike every term employed
hitherto, are not very commonly used in their present
sense in everyday life. Their adoption is desirable
not merely for the sake of convenience, but because
they help to stamp clearly on the mind a most illuminating
conception, that of the “margin,” which
supplies the clue to many complicated problems.
The last pound of sugar which the housewife purchased,
the fifth pound when the price was 8 cents, or the
sixth pound when the price was 7 cents, we call the
“marginal” pound of sugar. And the
increment of utility which she derives from buying
this marginal pound we call the “marginal utility”
of sugar to her. We are thus able to state the
fact that the more a person has of anything the less
urgently does he require a little more of it, in the
following formal terms:—