Children's Rights and Others eBook

Nora Archibald Smith
This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 147 pages of information about Children's Rights and Others.

Children's Rights and Others eBook

Nora Archibald Smith
This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 147 pages of information about Children's Rights and Others.

Some natures are antagonized by the shadow of a threat, even if it accompanies a reasonable order; and if we acknowledge that the oil of courtesy is a valuable lubricator in our dealings with grown people, it seems proper to suppose that it would not be entirely useless with children.  We cannot expect to get from them what we do not give ourselves, and it is idle to imagine that we can address them as we would a disobedient dog, and be answered in tones of dulcet harmony.

Again, what possible harm can there be in sometimes giving reasons for commands, when they are such as the child would appreciate?  We do not desire to bring him up under martial rule; and if he feels the wisdom of the order issued, he will be much more likely to obey it pleasantly.  Cases may frequently occur in which reasons either could not properly be given, or would be beyond the child’s power of comprehension; but if our treatment of him has been uniformly frank and affectionate, he will cheerfully obey, believing that, as our commands have been reasonable heretofore, there is good cause to suppose they may still be so.

Educational opinion tends, more and more every day, to the absolute conviction that the natural punishment, the effect which follows the cause, is the only one which can safely be used with children.

This is the method of Nature, severe and unrelenting it may be, but calm, firm, and purely just.  He who sows the wind must reap the whirlwind, and he who sows thistles may be well assured that he will never gather figs as his harvest.  The feeling of continuity, of sequence, is naturally strong in the child; and if we would lead him to appreciate that the law is as absolute in the moral as in the physical world, we shall find the ground already prepared for our purpose.

Much transgression of moral law in later years is due to the fatal hope in the evil-doer’s mind that he will be able to escape the consequences of his sin.  Could we make it clear from the beginning of life that there is no such escape, that the mills of the gods will grind at last, though the hopper stand empty for many a year,—­could we make this an absolute conviction of the mind, I am assured that it would greatly tend to lessen crime.

And this is one of the defects of arbitrary punishment, that it is sometimes withheld when the heart of the judge melts over the sinner, leading him to expect other possible exemptions in the future.  Is it not sometimes given in anger, also, when the culprit clearly sees it to be disproportionate to the crime?

Here appears the advantage of the natural punishment,—­it is never withheld in weak affection, it is never given in anger, it is entirely disassociated from personal feeling.  No poisoned arrow of injustice remains rankling in the child’s breast; no rebellious feeling that the parent has taken advantage of his superior strength to inflict the punishment:  it is perceived to be absolutely fair, and, being fair, it must be, although painful, yet satisfactory to that sense of justice which is a passion of childhood.

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Children's Rights and Others from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.